Alexander Nehamas is the author of the new book On Friendship. His other books include Only a Promise of Happiness and The Art of Living. He is the Carpenter Professor in the Humanities at Princeton University, and is a fellow of the American Academy of Arts & Sciences. He lives in Princeton, New Jersey.
Q:
Why did you decide to write about friendship?
A:
Several years ago, I was working on a book on love and beauty and noticed something
I had never noticed before. That was that as long as one loves someone (or
something: a work of art, for example), it is impossible to find them ugly: we
can’t love what we don’t actually find beautiful, whose beauty doesn’t strike
us.
And
it occurred to me that something like it is true of friendship as well: not
that we often choose our friends on the basis of their looks but that, once we
have become friends with someone, what earlier might have seemed like ugliness
in them disappears—it stops mattering—and their looks become more or less irrelevant
or even, in some cases, attractive.
That
suggested to me that friendship and erotic love are species of a broader kind
of love and it would be a good think to think about their relationship to one another.
Another
reason is that I became suspicious of the exclusive attention given both by philosophy
and by our culture in general to moral and political values.
These
values—especially justice—are supposed to be impartial and universal. They
dictate that we treat other people as we would treat ourselves and that we give
no special consideration to some individuals over others: on some basic level,
human beings are all alike and must be treated as such.
But
it has always seemed to me that these are not the only values there are. Some
values depend not on our similarities to, but on our differences from, each
other.
These
values promote individuality and distinction, the importance of making one’s
own particular mark in life instead of following unquestioningly the way others
have lived their lives.
And
these values apply only to some people and not to others. To find something
beautiful doesn’t require that everyone else find it beautiful too.
But
it isn’t a purely subjective affair either: I do want others to share my
attitude—but not all others: only my friends and some other people, people I
don’t yet know, but with whom I want to become friends on the basis of our
common taste.
Friendship
itself is another such value and it is also preferential rather than impartial:
it explicitly requires that I treat my friends differently from the way I treat
other people.
They
are values—originality, character, and style are also among them—that depend on
and accentuate our differences from one another, and I believe they deserve
much more attention that they have been given so far.
Finally,
several years ago my friend Tom, who is in a way the hero of my book, and I
gave a graduate seminar on friendship together and the idea of writing about
friendship became lodged in my mind. The book came about for all these reasons.
Q:
You write, "Some ancients thought that friendship binds the whole universe
together. We are more modest." How have ideas about friendship changed
over the centuries?
A:
We tend to think that relationships like friendship remain unchanged through
history—that what the ancient Greeks, the Renaissance British, and the
Facebook-users of today take friendship to be has stayed the same.
But,
in fact, what counts as friendship and what friends are expected to do for one
another has changed drastically over time—or at least, the behavior associated
with it has done so.
For
example, in ancient Rome and Renaissance Britain, friends were fundamentally
political allies whose plans you were expected to support and from whom you
expected the same: a friend was either a patron or a protégé.
Today,
by contrast, the idea that one should advance not because of any inherent
talent or ability but because of having the right friends is, at least
officially, anathema and we think of friendship as a relationship between
equals, not between a superior and an inferior.
The
relationship between friendship and sexuality also changes as we go from one
age to another. At various times—in the Middle Ages and as late as early modern
Britain among men or during the Victorian era among women—they were not considered
incompatible. Today, it is a cliché that “sex and friendship don’t go together.”
Like
all social relationships, friendship too depends on the needs and values of the
society within which it appears. But it would take a historian, not a
philosopher like me, to look at its evolution in the detail it deserves.
Q:
In the book, you write, "Friendship...has a double face." What are
its two faces?
A:
This is a characteristic not only of friendship but of…every non-moral value. At
least in theory, it is not possible to misuse a moral value: if I behave
justly, I am, at least to that extent, doing the right thing; I can’t act both
justly and wrongly.
By
contrast, friendship and beauty don’t give us such an assurance. A very
beautiful person or object can cause immense harm over time and a good friend,
as I argue in the book, can make us behave in objectionable ways.
As
the saying has it, a friend helps you move house; a good friend helps you move
a body. Or as E.M. Forster put it, “If I had to choose between betraying my
country and betraying my friend, I hope I should have the guts to betray my country.”
It
is therefore important to engage with these values carefully in order to avoid
such dangers. And it is particularly important when two values—a moral and a
non-moral one—conflict.
Moral
theory generally holds that its values are overriding and that in such a
conflict the moral value necessarily takes precedence: someone who is beautiful
and dangerous is, overall, a bad person.
I
think this is much too quick. We can’t just assume that this hierarchy is
always right. Sometimes, depending on the particular context, it is the
non-moral value that justifies a person and their life, despite their immoral aspects.
A
common example is the case of a painter who, like Paul Gauguin, abandons his
family and goes off to Tahiti in order to paint as he wants.
Had
Gauguin not proved to be a great painter, the immorality of his departure would
have marred his whole life. But since he succeeded in his work, it is not at
all clear to me that his was not a good, perhaps even a great, life.
Think,
too, of what E.M. Forster says: What would be the right thing to do if we ever
find ourselves confronting that choice?
A:
If we think of friendship as a positive relationship that involves treating
some people (or objects) preferentially, that is, differently from the way we
treat everyone else, I can’t at this point imagine a world without it. How that
preferential treatment expresses itself, however, will differ from one period
to another.
I
do think, however, that we need to put quotation marks around Facebook “friends.”
I am not saying that it is a bad thing
to have relationships—only that they are very loosely connected to how we understand
friendship today. They provide the same information, the same “facts,” to
everyone whom someone has “friended.”
That
is very different from friendship, which allows us to show each one of our
friends different aspects of ourselves. Every friendship is, strictly speaking,
a relationship between two individuals: no one else but us can have our
relationship.
That
is something Facebook can’t accomplish: the relationships it fosters, which
provide the same information to every “friend,” are not individual but
generic.
But
friendship is a relationship between individuals: it both depends on and
fosters individuality, who our friends are helps differentiate us, ideally in
admirable ways, from everyone else (which is why, despite its dangers, it
remains a great good).
I
don’t see how the social media in general, not just Facebook, can capture that
aspect of friendship’s nature.
Q:
What are you working on now?
A:
I am thinking about the non-moral values I mentioned above, considering writing
something about them more generally (and perhaps, I am afraid, more
abstractly).
I
am also thinking about Friedrich Nietzsche, on whom I have been writing for a
long time, and beginning to think about Martin Heidegger, whose Being and Time,
I taught for the first time this year.
But
I am also trying to relax a little between completing this book and beginning
another major project!
Q:
Anything else we should know?
A:
Not really.
--Interview with Deborah Kalb
No comments:
Post a Comment